Friday, 27 March 2009

Oneself as Another



An Abbreviated Review of Oneself as Another by Paul Ricoeur

This is all too brief, composed in haste, and unfair to the author. Hey, that makes it kind of like sermon prep, right?

The question 'how people change?' assumes that we know the 'what' and the 'who' of people. In other words, it assumes a tacit understanding of the nature of identity. This is precisely the topic reconsidered by Paul Ricoeur in his both cryptic and brilliant study Oneself as Another. The title summarizes the thesis of the book: "the selfhood of oneself implies otherness to such an intimate degree that one cannot be thought of without the other" (3). One could paraphrase this remark by saying that no individual defines or discovers himself. Ricoeur begins his argument by distinguishing between 'idem' and 'ipse' identity (idem meaning 'same' in Latin and ipse, 'oneself') Thus idem refers to identity as sameness. It replies to the question "what am I?". Ipse is identity as selfhood, the response to "who?". There is no doubt that our culture tends in varying degrees to conflate or isolate these two forms of identity. On the one hand, the corporate drone measuring his life by overtime hours and cigarette breaks may have lost sight of "who" he is. His identity has been reduced to 'whatness'. On the other, the American Idol contestant is so secure in "who" she is that the facts of pear-shaped hips and a squawking voice are irrelevant. So how then do we find out who we are?

Ricoeur starts by criticizing any approach that begins by positing the subject as 'I'. A notion of self only emerges by considering the self in relation "to the I-you of interlocution, to the identity of a historical person, to the self of responsibility" (11). In other words, there is not direct access to self-identity. We only know ourselves reflexively, only by relating to other persons, within a community, and in the mode of responsibility. All of this fits well in a covenant framework. Moreover, Ricoeur resists any attempt to ground oneself on epistemic certainty. The means of identity is attestation, a word Ricoeur tells us belongs to the grammar of "I believe-in" rather than "I believe-that." Attestation is supported by testimony "inasmuch as it is in the speech of the one giving testimony that one believes" (21). This point is significant and worth unpacking. Ricoeur admits that attestation is vulnerable and fragile: "there is no "true" testimony without "false" testimony" (22). Truth about oneself is not guaranteed as the apostle John is so vehement to iterate. Only one recourse exists against false testimony: another testimony "that is more credible" (22). To gloss with theological application - extraneous to the text - a person identifies himself by the testimony of the Holy Spirit and the communion of the Spirit within the church. These are the faithful witnesses through which--in terms of our union with Christ--we gain "the assurance of being oneself acting and suffering" (22).

Ricoeur confronts the paradox of sameness and selfhood from numerous angles. Sameness is a question of reidentification. We tend to think of it as a substance. Therefore, in terms of identity, the substance of a person is the sedimentation of habits and traits that become one's character. Ricoeur says, "By character I understand the distinctive marks which permit the reidentification of a human individual as being the same" (119). Yet, is character the only way of conceiving of selfhood? If so, "who" we are is simply a function of "what" we are. At this point Ricoeur introduces the concept of promise-keeping. The fact that a person can make and keep a promise tells us that he is irreducible to substance. A promise-maker is a "who", and the quality of this identity is manifest only in the context of trust. I think this point is worth emphasizing because of its application for believers. I take Paul's teaching to indicate the "who" of Christian identity is more important than the "what." The gospel is Christ making a promise for us that defines our identity in spite of our whatness. What are we? Sinners. Who are we? Christ. (Just so you know, Ricoeur specifically avoids any theological applications in the text, though he was a faithful 'reformed' believer in the broad sense. Look to Vanhoozer for theological application.)

I'll pull one final topic from Ricoeur. He devotes two studies to narrative identity. First of all, he asserts, "Self-understanding is an interpretation" (114). This interpretation occurs in the context of a community that identifies itself within a story. Ricoeur is earnest is saying that there are "imaginative variations" of any given narrative. Each of us finds ourselves active and passive as life unfolds. One of the paradoxes of our narrative identity is that naturally our lives have no conscious beginning or end. We do not remember our birth and we cannot foresee our death. Therefore, making sense of a life-plot depends on appropriating the stories we hear and read. This makes self-understanding a delicate issue. Ricoeur provocatively remarks, "To the loss of the identity of the character thus corresponds the loss of the configuration of the narrative and, in particular, a crisis of the closure of the narrative" (149). I think in terms of ministry this comment is pregnant with meaning. Is not the moment of crisis in faith - the unexpected death of a loved one, the discovery of a malignant illness, the frustration of encountering injustice - the loss of identity within a governing narrative and, more deeply, unanticipated skepticism about closure. The questions we ask prove this to be true: is God just? How could a good God allow this to happen? Why me? If this is true, part of how people change is growing to trust in the testimony of their story. The answer for pain is not finally belief about Providence or sovereignty. The balm of Gilead is a Person we believe-in.

Friday, 20 March 2009

Love Beyond Reason



Once I had read the DaVinci Code I had to read the rest of Dan Brown's books. I read the three of Sam Bourne's books one after the other in a month. It was similar once I read Faith and Doubt by John Ortberg I had to read more of his work. It is unusual to have felt this with a Christian author!

Love Beyond Reason is a fabulous title for a book. When we think about the love of God we are in danger of making it so like our love that we demeen it or as Calvinist, we can be in danger of elevating to such a height that we cannot experience it. John Ortberg wants to show that God's love, whilst being far from unreasonable, is above and beyond human comprehension.

Why does God love us? Why was Jesus willing to humble himself and appear in fashion as a man and to be convicted and cruelly put to death on the cross for sinners?

Ortberg does not answer these questions but he does help us to delve more deeply into them.

His illustration all the way through the book is that of his sister's rag-doll. It did not matter how ragged the doll became, she continued to love it. We are all rag-dolls he says. We all have our faults and our failings. We are all full of sin. Yet God loves us.

He begins the book addressing the nature of love. What it is and what it does. That it is caring and kind. That it is observant and willing to be inconvenienced for it's object.

Then he considers God and who and what God is. God's love has the holy Father of heaven caring for and touching this hideous world that has been marred by sin. His love changes lives and hearts. We see it in the New Testament where God the Son enters human suffering and experience. He lives a life different to any other human life. He displays a perfect example of human love. He'll even touch a leper.

Ortberg illustrates the Christian experience, as he does in his other books, with story after story from his own life and the lives of others. He shows how tough the Christian life can be but how the love of God meaning, and perhaps understanding, to all that we suffer in this present world.

The book is honest and humorous. His style is winsome and very entertaining. I think the only criticism I can make is that he becomes a little repetitive. One of the stories he tells here at length also appears in another of his books.

Why God loves his people is an impossible question to answer. That he loves us is a wonderful truth to proclaim and I found myself prticularly stirred and excited as Ortberg attempts to meditate on this deep topic. The impressive thing about his style is that he doesn't come across as the teacher wanting to show the ignorant what they do not already know. He comes across as the brother who wants to talk to us about God. Here is a conversation about God's love that we could all do with having. Tolle Lege.

Monday, 2 March 2009

Man and Rite: Natural Sacredness and Christian Liturgy


As I took up Louis Bouyer’s Rite and Man my leading questions concerned the nature of a liturgical anthropology. Assuming for a moment that Christian worship is not embroidery tacked onto theology, what does it mean for man to be, in the words of Schmemann, homo adorans? The book itself is an attempt by Bouyer of discerning the natural roots of Christian worship. His assumption is that if grace does not destroy nature, we should expect to find fundamentally human aspects within Christian worship. In other words, the Israelites and Canaanites may not disagree on every point. In no way does this thesis weaken the supernatural basis of Christianity. On the contrary, Bouyer conducts his research on the basis of an incarnational analogy. He iterates, “Indeed, the more perfectly we know the human aspects of Christianity, the more perfectly we shall understand that part of it which is the result of divine intervention” (3). God’s making wine for mirth in no way denies His ability subsequently to take up a Jewish cup and declare the new covenant.

With regard to the incarnational analogy, Bouyer warns of twin dangers of monophysite and Nestorian ‘sacrality’. On the one hand, a monophysite vision emphasizes the supernatural character of Christianity to the extent that nature becomes inconsequential. Thus creation and humanity are reciprocally devalued. On the other, a Nestorian view asserts both divine and human aspects, but fails to coordinate the two. Against both of these exaggerations a truly Christian understanding of the sacred allows for supernatural revelation to occur in nature: “But the signs of what is sacred, those spontaneous signs which are consequent to man’s primitive and basic experience of his utter dependence upon a God who is both distinct and transcendent become charged with new significance” (11). Bread is bread. Wine is wine. And both are Christ.

Bouyer spends his first few chapters tracing the history of comparative religions. He notes how 17th century skepticism concluded with relativism, that all religions were basically the same. This, however, quickly gave way in the 18th century to the thesis that religion was a priestly construct. A tendency arose for historians and early anthropologists was to deride religion as a product of primitive humanity, a mere stage preceding enlightenment (Compte). Therefore, Bouyer recognizes some good in thinkers like Freud and Jung who at least pried room for discussion concerning the role of religion in man’s consciousness. Writing in the mid 20th century, Bouyer rejoices, “One cannot properly speak about a genesis of the idea of God. This idea is found in the most elementary manifestation of a religion consciousness” (25). Elsewhere he says, “Religion is the spontaneous response which man’s existential situation elicits as soon as this latter is fully accepted in its reality” (31). Again, these remarks do not locate Bouyer on the silty ground of pluralism. His point is one shared by Calvin, Turretin, and reformed theologians today. Man is religious.

One of the most interesting discussions in Bouyer’s book concerns the nature of a religious rite. It’s easy to assume a Christian context for this discussion, but one must recognize that Bouyer’s project is to speak first at the level of what reformed theologians call common grace. On this turf he says, “In other words, a rite is not simply one type of action among many others. It is the typical human action, inasmuch as it is connected with the word as the expression and realization of man in the world, and to the degree that this expression and realization are immediately and fundamentally religious” (57). Several aspects of the quotation are worth considering. First, a rite is “the typical human action.” Human behavior is symbolically mediated and infused with meaning that transcends mundane tasks. We are liturgical beings. Moreover, rite and word are inextricably linked. Words here do not signify abstract concepts, but rather are creative and dense (c.f. 61); they profess what is occurring. Thus the Israelites repeat the story of the Exodus as they perform the Passover meal not only because they are already redeemed but also because God continues to enact His covenant in their midst. Another salient point Bouyer repeats is that the actions involved in rites are neither extrinsic nor arbitrary. He confesses, “The symbolism always exists prior to the meaning placed upon it. When this meaning is further defined, the symbol becomes a sign” (63). Again, “In no way were the words thought to infuse a wholly accidental, unprepared meaning into actions that were not prepared to receive it” (64). Anyone who knows the development of Christology takes this point. As Jaroslav Pelikan has masterfully articulated, only in the context of worshiping Christ did theologians realize what they were doing.

Now these descriptions of religious rites may scare evangelicals. Snippets make Bouyer sound like a devotee of religious syncretism. But this is to take a fish for a snake. Bouyer’s sole purpose is to use a phenomenological approach to religion so as to see the full meaning of the Christian rite and in the end to assert its uniqueness. In doing so I believe he clarifies some of the questions we should and shouldn’t bring to the Scriptures. For example, on the grounds that man is by nature liturgical, Bouyer is able to avoid the scholastic distinctions commentators make in trying to define the functions and purposes of Levitical regulations. Bouyer reminds us: “Sacrifice is not originally a subtle notion; it is a fact, a fact whose material reality should be taken into account before hasty attempts are made to give it spiritual explanation” (84). This material aspect of Israelite worship is not something we should dismiss as naïve and pre-critical; it’s something we share. If nothing else, the reader walks away from Bouyer convinced that liturgy is not a game theologians play to educate the simple: it’s not theological dress-up. On the contrary, “The liturgical drama does nothing more than make the divine story, which is to remain the soul of the rite, evoked as it may be, concrete and perfectly explicit” (100).

Wednesday, 25 February 2009

I See Satan Fall Like Lightning



On the back cover of my edition of I See Satan Fall Like Lightning one of the reviews declares, “Girard enables us to talk for the first time about a ‘phenomenology of redemption.’” I think this is right. Girard offers an anthropological description of how the gospel transforms human interaction and thus societies. His approach is neither theological nor dependent upon Scripture as revelation. Rather, he uses Scripture as one document among others; yet, in the process they glisten with extraordinary light. One should not fault Girard too early. His conclusions are worth hearing even if one disagrees with minor or major points.

Girard asserts that by nature humans desire what other people have along with what other people themselves desire. One the one hand, this is the basis of role models, and it allows children to mature into adults. On the other, it forms a relationship of rivalry in which the one coveting desires his neighbor and the neighbor, by way of response, increases his own desire for the object. Compliment a man’s wife and he suddenly finds her more attractive! This dialectic of desire can quickly escalate into a kind of competition, especially if something scandalizes one’s desire. If emotions are strong enough, inhibition gives way to violence. Therefore, by characterizing human nature as ‘mimetic’, Girard concludes that society and human relations are founded on rivalry, competition, and finally violence.

If desire is fundamentally mimetic—copies what others themselves desire, this means that groups of people value common objects. Thus ‘scandals’ do not simply confront individuals but societies as a whole. Pressure builds as desire is frustrated. The result is often to trigger a “single victim mechanism” whereby blame converges on a single individual, usually a marginal victim. This is also where Girard introduces his conception of Satan. Satan, for Girard, is the impulse of blame and accusation. Distracting attention from the true contagion, he isolates and accuses a scapegoat instead. He is a principle of disorder and order. He harnesses the power of mimetic desire and then orders human passion by releasing it in an act of violence. This violence appears to remove the problem. In the end, however, it merely prolongs the process of coveting, rivalry, and blame. Evangelicals may be distressed by Girard’s assertion that, while Satan is real, he has no being. But the difficulty is partially alleviated if one remembers that Girard proposes an anthropological analysis of violence, not a theological one. Measuring Satan’s ontological activity is hazardous at best; most important, is positing the reality of a principle of sin and disorder that is targeted by God’s redemptive work.

One may ask where Girard gets his data for this analysis. One of his main sources is ancient myth. Against most anthropologists and comparative religion scholars Girard does not reduce myth to fantasy, but contends that myth represents real violence. It is not by accident that so many founding stories begin with murder and fratricide. In doing so these stories themselves prolong the cycle of violence and consumptive sacrifice. Here in the argument Girard introduces the gospels into the analysis. He insists that the gospel narratives are unique in that they do not condone the actions of the crowd or even the disciples, but rather justify the victim. Moreover, what is true of the New Testament finds early resonance in the stories of marginal figures like Joseph, Moses, and the prophets. Focused in the narrative of Christ, the gospels provide a principle of mimetic desire for humankind that subverts the power of egotistic desire. In Jesus, humanity discovers an anthropology derived from sacrificial love and the singular will to obey another. At the same time, Satan’s work is reckoned for what it is: evil.

One should not feel the need from Girard to shape his entire theology of redemption or atonement on the subversion of mimetic desire. What any Christian can take away, though, is the satisfaction that only the Christian Scriptures adequately estimate the bondage of the human will and provide a model for human interaction that is loving rather than competitive. As Christians, we follow Christ in laying down our lives for others. Girard reminds us that this ethic is a Christian contribution to the world.

Tuesday, 17 February 2009

Leviticus as Literature


Mary Douglas’s title Leviticus as Literature may appear oxymoronic or perhaps just moronic. For most readers Leviticus is more of an instruction manual than a piece of artistry. The layers of cultic instruction, moral laws, and interspersed stories of spewed fire obfuscate not only creativity but also theological meaning in the text. Even Calvin found it hard to comment on the book. This is not the sentiment of Douglas, though, who sees Leviticus as outlining a “modern religion” with emphases extending so far as animal justice. Yet, it is not Douglas’s ethical sensitivity which gives merit to the book--in fact, this may be her weakness. Rather, it is Douglas’s training as an anthropologist along with her literary sensitivity that stimulate fresh insight into a dusty text.

Anthropologically, Douglas has a different lens than standard commentators including even the doyen of Levitical studies, Jacob Milgrom. For example, rather that using the paucity of imperatives in Leviticus to draw inferences about authorship or dating, Douglas reads Leviticus comparatively against cultures where “direct commands are not necessary” because “authority is clear and everyone knows what is to be done” (35). Likewise, she excuses gaps in the text, reminding contemporary readers that a common cultural identity “makes explicit verbalization unnecessary” (38). Two points of particular interest are her anthropological discussions of the positive uses and benefits of divination (not in the ethical but pragmatic sense!) as well as her discussion of the problems that occur by de-mythologizing the presence of demons in the world. Concerning the latter topic, by eliminating the function of demons in the popular imagination for causing disorder, decay, and doom the Hebrew writers raise new questions relating to the goodness of creation and origin of evil. Douglas makes a consistent effort to read the impurity laws of Leviticus in harmony with the clear Genesis teaching that all of creation is good in essence and purpose. Another important insight she provides is the concrete nature of the command to love one’s neighbor. Douglas notes that in the text love does not denote an emotion, but rather a “legal idea of free and un-coerced willingness” (43).

The most provocative sections in the book, for me at least, are those dealing with the analogical structure of Leviticus. In chapter two Douglas goes to great pains to convince the reader that there are two equally valid kinds of reasoning, analogical and rational-instrumental thinking. Both occur within human societies and both are capable of focusing analytical questions. On the one hand, analogical reasoning projects patterns on the world. It is horizontal, concentric, hierarchical and usually accompanies a mytho-poetic worldview. The intellectual history of Eastern cultures exhibits this kind of reasoning. For example, Douglas notes, “Chinese mathematical thought traditionally uses analogy to construct parallel instances, and then to scrutinize them systematically, character by character, to check exactly where the correspondence lies” (31). [This sounds strikingly similar to Christian figural reading!] On the other, rational-instrumental thinking isolates, breaks down, and defines an object. As one might expect, Douglas argues that the logic of Leviticus depends on correlation and analogy, not logical or natural causation. She says, “Only the whole system of analogies in which it nests will show how it is to be read” (20). Elsewhere she extends the textual principle to Levitical cosmography: “Nothing can be justified in this universe except in terms of the proper position in the spatial/temporal order whose rightness is the only justification for anything” (39).

The application of this analogical reasoning is where Douglas’s exegesis becomes exciting. She sees a layered, tri-part pattern repeated from the initial covenant proceedings at Sinai to the structure of the tabernacle and further into the bodies of the sacrificial animals. This final correspondence is Douglas’s unique contribution to commentary on Leviticus, and she lends anthropological support to the hypothesis by drawing several parallels with totem-based cultures. She iterates, “In the space of the animal’s body [the writer] finds analogies with the tabernacle and the history of God’s revelation to Israel” (45). There are two analogical referents to the trizone anatomy: one is the way the animal parts would appear as the worshiper ‘enters’ the body with a knife; the other is the appearance of the pieces as they are arranged on the altar. The first instance mirrors entering the tabernacle from the courtyard, the second the ascent up Sinai during the initial covenant proceedings. For this reason, Douglas recommends seeing ‘inner’ and ‘upper’ as complementary.

All this may be difficult to conceptualize, so allow me to summarize the imagery. In the case of ‘entering’ the animal, the head and meat sections, which physically give access to the body, reflect the courtyard of the tabernacle and the base of Mt. Sinai where all God’s people could assemble. Thus all worshipers can consume these sections. Moving to the midriff area, one finds the dense fat that surrounds the kidneys and liver loab. These are altar portions. They are not for human consumption. Douglas imagines the layers of fat as analogous to the smoke of incense in the holy place and the cloud covering Sinai. Moreover, these ‘zones’ functioned as boundary markers separating common grounds from areas where only the elders--in the case of Sinai--and priests--in the case of the tabernacle--had access. Could the two kidneys represent the table and candelabra? Visually this works. Finally, the entrails, intestines and genitals, in which the fecundity, emotions, and feelings were supposed to reside, are analogous to the holy of holies. Here we see God as the source of vitality, life, and affection. Thus ‘entering’ the animal is a mimetic journey up Sinai or into the Tabernacle. While this may sound like Cabbalist mysticism to 21st century evangelicals, Douglas gives anthropological data of other cultures that project cosmic structures onto human and animal bodies. Personally, I like the thought of the physical construction of animal parts on the sacrificial altar as visibly reproducing the covenant proceedings of Sinai. Lest one be too skeptical of the thesis, Moses did after all see a heavenly pattern!

The parallels continue, though my time for writing fades. Douglas claims, “The structure of the text [Leviticus as a whole] is an analogy of the structure of the desert tabernacle” (198). Following the literary uses of ringlets and chiasm, she asserts that the narrative portions of Leviticus divide the book into three sections, each corresponding to a “screen” between subsequent sections of the tabernacle. For instance, the first section treats general sacrifices that pertain to all Israelites, mirroring the Tabernacle’s courtyard, etc. Microcosm upon microcosm, Douglas’s analogical reasoning builds a coherent reading of Leviticus. Allow me to conclude with a quotation: “Learning the book becomes a way of internalizing the tabernacle, in the same way as the spiritual Jerusalem was distinguished from the physical Jerusalem at the center of the world. At the same time, moving round the tabernacle with the book, they are also moving round Mt. Sinai, and even had access to part of it that only Moses had” (230). Perhaps the anonymous 14th century author and mystic of the Cloud of Unknowing was not so peculiar after all for basing a pattern of contemplative prayer on the physical dimensions of the Ark of the Covenant.

Orthodoxy



Imagine a book written arguing the case for Christianity, addressing the arrogance of unbelieving science and the ignorance of those who trust it, the worldliness and materialism of modern society, the emptiness of Buddhism and Confucianism despite their popularity, and the suitableness of Christ-centred, biblical Christianity. All told with true style and wit.

I'm sitting in Starbucks at the Quartermile in Edinburgh having just finished (at last) reading GK Chesterton's Orthodoxy and I am amazed at two things:
1 - How much I agree with this convert to Roman Catholicism
2 - That this book was first published, not in 2008 but in 1908

I won't say he's a theologian, but he is not here arguing points of theology. He makes just a passing remark or two against Calvinism and the Reformation for which we must forgive him. But he is an apologist extraordinaire.

Many Christian apologists are not taken seriously. Some put their argument across with such gravitas and academic lingo that you get lost in their rhetoric. Others pretend the arguments are so simple that they fail to address the issues. Chesterton is at once engaging and stylish in his writing whilst, at once, challenging but plain in his argument.

The reality of spirituality, of miracle, the tenacity of the scriptures, the sensibleness of the gospel and the helpfulness of the doctrine of original sin are all covered in this short work. Chesterton shows that beginning as a mere philosopher, every conclusion he ever reached by himself, he found to be the same truth as was taught in the Christian religion.

I want to give an example of his argument. Toward the end of the book Chesterton discusses the likelihood of miracle:
Somehow or other an extraordinary idea has arisen that the disbelievers in miracle consider them coldly and fairly, while believers in miracles accept them only in connection with some dogma. The fact is quite the other way. The believers in miracle accept them (rightly or wrongly) because they have evidence for them. The disbelievers in miracles deny them (rightly or wrongly) because they have a doctrine against them...
The plain, popular course is to trust the peasant's word about the ghost as far as you trust the peasant's word about the landlord...
If it comes to human testimony there is a choking cataract of human testimony in favour of the supernatural. If you reject it, you can only mean one of two things. You reject the peasant's story about the ghost either because the man is a peasant or because the story is a ghost story. That is you either you either deny the main principle of democracy, or you affirm the main principle of materialism - the abstract impossibility of a miracle. You have a perfect right to do so; but in that case you are the dogmatist. It is we Christians who accept all actual evidence - it is you rationalists who refuse actual evidence being constrained to do so by your creed..."

People - get ready to think. Tolle lege.

Monday, 2 February 2009

The Self as Agent




John MacMurray is a Scottish philosopher (d. 1976) who deserves a wider hearing. His critique is brazen, nothing short of declaring the need to invert the fundamental assumption of modern philosophy. Following Descartes philosophy has built its house on the assumption of the 'self' as isolated thinker. In other words, what is the one ground of certainty that truth can stand on? Myself as a cognative being. The deadend along this road is Kant who, while positing the real existence of a world outside of humans, nonetheless concludes that this world is inaccessible to us. Reason is only helpful insofar as it follows concepts (rules) that in turn allow us to synthesize (schematize) experience according to unavoidably human categories. Transcendence is beyond us. The best we can do is - believing in the laws of non-contradition and moral law (faith alone!) - is hope our moral rectitude find reward if there is anything beyond us. Post-Kant, western philosophy dissolves. By the time MacMurray gives the Gifford lectures in the 1950's, philosophy is divorced between logical positivists (let's just clarify what we're saying) who maintain the philosophic method without ultimate concerns and existentialist who hold tight the concerns but without a method. What to do?

MacMurray's contention is that philosophy needs a new foundation, not the isolated thinker but the self as agent. This assertion presupposes that theory and practice cannot be unrelated. Humans are not fundamentally abstract thinkers, but persons with thoughts, intentions, emotions, and actions. Responding to the "crisis of the personal," MacMurray's goal is to replace the 'I think' with the 'I act' as the first principle of philosophy. Two things need to be said here. First, MacMurray's understanding of action is inclusive. What he means by this is, whereas action necessarily includes the rational faculties of a person, the same is not true of thought. He explains,

"The concept of 'action' is inclusive. As an ideal limit of personal being, it is the concept of an unlimited rational being, in which all the capacities of the Self are in full and unrestricted employment" (87).

While certainly no one achieves this limit in life, the construct is illuminating. Is this not the intent of so many New Testament passages that assert belief results in action? MacMurray's point is that knowledge is not abstract. The test of adequacy of any philosophy comes by applying theory to the world of action. Does theory clarify the telos of action? Does theory enable people to achieve that telos?

Second, MacMurray insists that "any philosophy which takes the 'I think' as its first principle, must remain formally a philosophy without a second person" (72). If you are an "I think" and I am an "I think", all either of us can do is "I think" about the other! Anyone married knows how far this is from personal knowledge of a spouse. Extending the point, however, Macmurray opines, "The idea of 'God' is the idea of a universal 'Thou' to which all particular persons stand in personal relation." Unfortunately, Kant did not have a category by which to schematize this!

There is plenty more to discuss in MacMurray. This book is only a prelude to a second volume that focuses the discussion of persons within the context of community. Perhaps the best way to conclude, however, is to ask what this means for theologians. Here are two brief suggestions:

1. If persons are agents (actors) and knowledge is not theoretical, theology should not be abstract. God is a trinity of persons and we are persons as well. Knowledge, therefore, must be inter-personal.

2. The divide of theory and practice is a modern contruct to be deconstructed. Practice is the fulfillment of theory and if in practice a theory doesn't work, it needs to be abandoned. This is precisely the wager of Christian faith. We believe that human fulfillment only comes by communion with God in Jesus Christ. If Christ does not have the power to change lives - not just minds - he is not worth following. This sounds blasphemous unless, that is, one really believes and has experienced the power of the resurrection.

Finally, let me end with a quotation worthy of resounding down the corridors of ever liberal religious studies department in the Western world:

"Is it not more likely that our capacity for scepticism is as unlimited as our credulity, and increases, like all our powers, with exercize"

Wednesday, 28 January 2009

For the Life of the World




Alexander Schmemann is an Orthodox theologian that every Protestant should read if for no other reason than the paucity of decent reformed literature on ecclesiology, sacraments, and liturgy. The great spiritual battles of our generation do not divide on Catholic/Protestant lines (much less Orthodox), and for scouting more insidious neighbors like secularism, there is no better guide than Schmemann. The purpose of For the Life of the World is to describe what the sacraments mean for a Christian 'worldview'. Schmemann presupposes that man is not primarily a thinker or maker but a worshiper, homo adorans. Likewise, creation exists in order for man to experience, worship, and ultimately commune with God. Schmemann declares the great heresy of our day to be the supposition that something real exists outside of the sacramental world; in other words, the supposition that one can know anything apart from the love and enjoyment of God. Thus rather than being an aside within the dogmatic category of 'Church', sacraments for Schmemann are the mysteries that most clearly refract the Light of the World. The church is a cosmology, not ecclesiology; she is the vantage point that makes sense of time and space in our militant age.

There are two terms that must be defined in order to understand Schmemman, worship and sacrament. Worship is the essence of knowledge for humans, a knowledge itself defined as communion with God and the world. This connection of knowledge and world means that humans cannot experience God without the senses: "We need water and oil, bread and wine in order to be in communion with God and to know Him." Yet this is not some kind of shallow empiricism. Matter by itself signfies nothing but death. Sacrament, then, is Gods epiphany in matter. A physical form expresses, communicates, and reveals God's splendor without losing its own ontological reality. This latter point is far from superfluous. Only bread as bread is able to signify Christ's body. Only wine, his blood. As such these mysteries elicit wonder, awe, and joy - not to mention gratification - while imparting knowledge of God.

Why might a reformed person fear Schmemann? Perhaps because he's too sacramental. He doesn't concede any room to a secular order of common grace. No ghetto hedges sacred bread within profane. Once a person becomes catechized within the church, all bread signifies Christ, though not all is liturgical. Time gains meter by the already, not-yet. Space is filled with the presence of God. Life becomes a crescendo moving toward the final feast of Lamb and bride. Christ death is For the Life of the World.

Thursday, 15 January 2009

Isaac Watts on Prayer




I don't know a single Christian who does not struggle with prayer. For some, the practice of prayer is like an unknown language. Others wrestle with the plausibility of prayer: does God need our prayer, use them, learn from them, etc. These questions are not new and if for no other reason than an outside perspective (temporal as well as cultural), we will benefit from revisiting Watts's treatise A GUIDE TO PRAYER.

The book is lucid in style and structure just as anyone would expect who has sung Watts's hymns. He begins with the nature of prayer and moves to the gift of prayer (nature of gift, forms, matter). A striking feature of the discussion is just how pastoral it is. For example, to help his readers remember the kinds and ordering of prayer, Watts provides a memorable ditty:

Call upon God, adore, confess,
Petition, plead, and then declare
You are the Lord's give thanks and bless,
And let Amen confirm the prayer.

Likewise, one of his rules--for the weaker sheep like myself in the flock--is: "do not affect to pray long, for the sake of length, or to stretch out i/our matter by labour and toil of thought, beyond the furniture of your own spirit."

Overall, I'd recommend this text for any Christian, reformed or not, who wrestles with the what and how of prayer. The framework of Watts thought is distinctively Calvinistic, but the substance of his thought and intent has the richness of a spiritual tradition ebbing from the 14th c. pastoral writings of Walter Hilton and Richard Rolle. As for myself, I plan on taking segments of the text and practicing them bit by bit. Prayer is not something one ever masters. Yet, real progress can occur, and for this, Watts is a faithful guide.