
An Abbreviated Review of Oneself as Another by Paul Ricoeur
This is all too brief, composed in haste, and unfair to the author. Hey, that makes it kind of like sermon prep, right?
The question 'how people change?' assumes that we know the 'what' and the 'who' of people. In other words, it assumes a tacit understanding of the nature of identity. This is precisely the topic reconsidered by Paul Ricoeur in his both cryptic and brilliant study Oneself as Another. The title summarizes the thesis of the book: "the selfhood of oneself implies otherness to such an intimate degree that one cannot be thought of without the other" (3). One could paraphrase this remark by saying that no individual defines or discovers himself. Ricoeur begins his argument by distinguishing between 'idem' and 'ipse' identity (idem meaning 'same' in Latin and ipse, 'oneself') Thus idem refers to identity as sameness. It replies to the question "what am I?". Ipse is identity as selfhood, the response to "who?". There is no doubt that our culture tends in varying degrees to conflate or isolate these two forms of identity. On the one hand, the corporate drone measuring his life by overtime hours and cigarette breaks may have lost sight of "who" he is. His identity has been reduced to 'whatness'. On the other, the American Idol contestant is so secure in "who" she is that the facts of pear-shaped hips and a squawking voice are irrelevant. So how then do we find out who we are?
Ricoeur starts by criticizing any approach that begins by positing the subject as 'I'. A notion of self only emerges by considering the self in relation "to the I-you of interlocution, to the identity of a historical person, to the self of responsibility" (11). In other words, there is not direct access to self-identity. We only know ourselves reflexively, only by relating to other persons, within a community, and in the mode of responsibility. All of this fits well in a covenant framework. Moreover, Ricoeur resists any attempt to ground oneself on epistemic certainty. The means of identity is attestation, a word Ricoeur tells us belongs to the grammar of "I believe-in" rather than "I believe-that." Attestation is supported by testimony "inasmuch as it is in the speech of the one giving testimony that one believes" (21). This point is significant and worth unpacking. Ricoeur admits that attestation is vulnerable and fragile: "there is no "true" testimony without "false" testimony" (22). Truth about oneself is not guaranteed as the apostle John is so vehement to iterate. Only one recourse exists against false testimony: another testimony "that is more credible" (22). To gloss with theological application - extraneous to the text - a person identifies himself by the testimony of the Holy Spirit and the communion of the Spirit within the church. These are the faithful witnesses through which--in terms of our union with Christ--we gain "the assurance of being oneself acting and suffering" (22).
Ricoeur confronts the paradox of sameness and selfhood from numerous angles. Sameness is a question of reidentification. We tend to think of it as a substance. Therefore, in terms of identity, the substance of a person is the sedimentation of habits and traits that become one's character. Ricoeur says, "By character I understand the distinctive marks which permit the reidentification of a human individual as being the same" (119). Yet, is character the only way of conceiving of selfhood? If so, "who" we are is simply a function of "what" we are. At this point Ricoeur introduces the concept of promise-keeping. The fact that a person can make and keep a promise tells us that he is irreducible to substance. A promise-maker is a "who", and the quality of this identity is manifest only in the context of trust. I think this point is worth emphasizing because of its application for believers. I take Paul's teaching to indicate the "who" of Christian identity is more important than the "what." The gospel is Christ making a promise for us that defines our identity in spite of our whatness. What are we? Sinners. Who are we? Christ. (Just so you know, Ricoeur specifically avoids any theological applications in the text, though he was a faithful 'reformed' believer in the broad sense. Look to Vanhoozer for theological application.)
I'll pull one final topic from Ricoeur. He devotes two studies to narrative identity. First of all, he asserts, "Self-understanding is an interpretation" (114). This interpretation occurs in the context of a community that identifies itself within a story. Ricoeur is earnest is saying that there are "imaginative variations" of any given narrative. Each of us finds ourselves active and passive as life unfolds. One of the paradoxes of our narrative identity is that naturally our lives have no conscious beginning or end. We do not remember our birth and we cannot foresee our death. Therefore, making sense of a life-plot depends on appropriating the stories we hear and read. This makes self-understanding a delicate issue. Ricoeur provocatively remarks, "To the loss of the identity of the character thus corresponds the loss of the configuration of the narrative and, in particular, a crisis of the closure of the narrative" (149). I think in terms of ministry this comment is pregnant with meaning. Is not the moment of crisis in faith - the unexpected death of a loved one, the discovery of a malignant illness, the frustration of encountering injustice - the loss of identity within a governing narrative and, more deeply, unanticipated skepticism about closure. The questions we ask prove this to be true: is God just? How could a good God allow this to happen? Why me? If this is true, part of how people change is growing to trust in the testimony of their story. The answer for pain is not finally belief about Providence or sovereignty. The balm of Gilead is a Person we believe-in.